Essentially Embodied Kantian Selves and The Fantasy of Transhuman Selves

 
Название публикации (др.)Сущностно инкорпорированные кантовские самости и фантазия о трансчеловеческих самостях
Код статьиS271326680021060-6-1
DOI10.18254/S271326680021060-6
Тип публикации Статья
Статус публикации Опубликовано
Авторы
Аффилиация:
Адрес: США
Название журналаТрансцендентальный журнал
ВыпускТом 3 Выпуск 3
Аннотация

By “essentially embodied Kantian selves,” I mean necessarily and completely embodied rational conscious, self-conscious, sensible (i.e., sense-perceiving, imagining, and emoting), volitional or willing, discursive (i.e., conceptualizing, judging, and inferring) animals, or persons, innately possessing dignity, and fully capable not only of free agency, but also of a priori knowledge of analytic and synthetic a priori truths alike, with egocentric centering in manifestly real orientable space and time. The basic theory of essentially embodied Kantian selves was spelled out by Kant over the course of slightly less than two decades, between 1768 and 1787, but above all, it flows from an empirical realist and metaphysical reading of the “Refutation of Idealism” that Kant inserted into the Postulates of Empirical Thought section in the 1787 edition of the first Critique. In my opinion, all rational but also “human, all-too-human” creatures like us are, synthetic a priori necessarily, essentially embodied Kantian selves. Let’s call that the essentially embodied Kantian selves thesis, or for short, EEKST. If EEKST is true, then it’s synthetic a priori impossible for the selves of creatures like us to exist independently of our own living organismic animal bodies or beyond the deaths of those bodies, whether temporarily or permanently, by any means whatsoever. Indeed, the very ideas of disembodied selves, their survival after death, and of human immortality, while minimally logically consistent, are in fact conceptually empty and incoherent, even over and above the synthetic a priori impossibility of such things, since the term “myself” indexically picks out an essentially embodied Kantian self, all of whose core features require grounding in a particular living organismic animal body. According to the recent and contemporary movement of transhumanism, the selves of creatures like us can not only exist independently of our bodies, as functional systems of representational content that are inherently able to be implemented or realized in digital-mechanical technology and uploadable to servers, but also to survive accidental or natural human death in server-limbo, then be downloaded into technologically enhanced partially mechanical humanoid bodies or even into wholly artificially-created completely mechanical non-humanoid bodies, survive in these new implementations or realizations for an indefinitely long time, repeat that process, and possibly even become immortal. Transhumanism is in fact metaphysically equivalent to Swedenborgianism, which Kant so effectively criticizes and wittily derides in his 1766 book, Dreams of a Spirit-Seer Elucidated by Dreams of Metaphysics. Moreover, and more importantly, if EEKST is true, then, just like Swedenborgianism, transhumanism is not only conceptually empty and incoherent, but also synthetic a priori impossible. And what’s more, it’s also existentially and morally reprehensible. In short, then, the belief in transhuman selves is nothing but a reprehensible noumenal fantasy or Hirngespinst.

Аннотация (др.)

Под сущностно инкорпорированными кантовскими «Я» я подразумеваю животных или личностей с необходимостью и полностью инкорпорированным рациональным сознанием, самосознанием, чувствами (т.е. обладающих органами чувств, воображением и эмоциями), волей или желанием, дискурсивным мышлением (способных к концептуализации, суждению и умозаключениям), обладающих врожденным достоинством и способных не только к свободной деятельности, но и к априорному знанию аналитических и синтетических априорных истин, с центрированных эгоцентрически в явно реальном ориентируемом пространстве и времени. Основная теория сущностно инкорпорированных «Я» была сформулирована Кантом на протяжении почти двух десятилетий, между 1768 и 1787 гг., но прежде всего она вытекает из эмпирико-реалистического и метафизического прочтения «Опровержения идеализма», которое Кант вставил в раздел «Постулаты эмпирического мышления» в издании первой «Критики» 1787 г. По моему мнению, все рациональные, но также и «человеческие, слишком человеческие» существа, подобные нам, с необходимостью синтетически априори являются по существу инкорпорированными кантовскими «Я». Назовем это тезисом о сущностно инкорпорированных кантовских самостях, или, для краткости, EEKST. Если EEKST верен, то синтетически априорно невозможно, чтобы «Я» таких существ, как мы, существовало независимо от наших собственных, живых животных тел (организмов) или после смерти этих тел, временной или постоянной, каким бы то ни было способом. Действительно, сама идея о неинкорпорированных «Я», их выживании после смерти или о человеческом бессмертии, хотя и являются минимально логически последовательными, на самом деле концептуально пусты и бессвязны, даже помимо синтетической априорной невозможности таких вещей, поскольку термин «Я» указывает на инкорпорированное кантовское «Я», все основные характеристики которого требуют укорененности в конкретном живом органическом животном теле.

Согласно современному движению трансгуманизма, «Я» таких существ, как мы, не только может существовать независимо от наших тел, в виде функциональных систем репрезентативного содержания, которые могут быть реализованы посредством цифро-механических технологий и загружены на серверы, но и пережить смерть человека в состоянии серверного лимба, а затем будучи загруженными в технологически усовершенствованные, частично механические, гуманоидные тела или даже в искусственно созданные полностью механические негуманоидные тела, выжить в этих новых реализациях или воплощениях в течение неопределенно долгого времени, причем процесс этот можно повторять вплоть до бессмертия. В действительности, трансгуманизм с метафизической точки зрения эквивалентен Сведенборгианству, которое Кант так эффективно критиковал и остроумно высмеивал в своей книге «Сны духовидца, разъясненные снами метафизики» (1766 г.). Более того, что еще более важно, если EEKST верен, то, как и Сведенборгианство, трансгуманизм не только концептуально пуст и некогерентен, но и синтетически априорно невозможен. Более того, он также экзистенциально и морально предосудителен. Короче говоря, вера в трансчеловеческие личности – это не что иное, как предосудительная ноуменальная фантазия или привидение (Hirngespinst).

Ключевые словаImmanuel Kant, Selves, Embodiment, Swedenborgianism, Transhumanism
Ключевые слова (др.)Кант, самость, инкорпорирование, Сведенборгианство, трансгуманизм
Получено15.09.2022
Дата публикации29.12.2022
Кол-во символов85263
Цитировать   Скачать pdf Для скачивания PDF необходимо авторизоваться
100 руб.
При оформлении подписки на статью или выпуск пользователь получает возможность скачать PDF, оценить публикацию и связаться с автором. Для оформления подписки требуется авторизация.

Оператором распространения коммерческих препринтов является ООО «Интеграция: ОН»

1
hanna1

“Who Was Swedenborg?” (Swedenborg Foundation, 2022)

2
hanna2

“Face of the Future” (Guardian, 2018)

3 In Stockholm there dwells a certain [Swedenborg], a gentleman of comfortable means and independent position. For the last twenty years or more he has, as he tells us, devoted himself exclusively to cultivating the closest contact with spirits and with the souls of the dead, and, in exchange, to giving them information about this present world, to composing hefty volumes devoted to his discoveries, and periodically travelling to London in order to supervise their publication…. [Swedenborg] distinguishes between the outer and inner memory in humankind. A person has outer memory as someone belonging to the visible world, whereas a person has inner memory in connection with the spirit-world. [Swedenborg’s] own superiority consists in the fact that, already in this life, he sees himself as a person who belongs to the community of spirits and that he is recognized as someone belonging to that community. It is also in this inner memory that everything, which has vanished from outer memory, is conserved, none of a person’s representations ever getting lost. After death, the memory of everything which had ever entered his soul and which had so far remained concealed from him, goes to make up the complete book of his life (DSS 2: 354, 362).
4 As humans, we are defined by, among other things, our desire to transcend our humanity. Mythology, religion, fiction and science offer different versions of this dream. Transhumanism—a social movement predicated on the belief that we can and should leave behind our biological condition by merging with technology—is a kind of feverish amalgamation of all four. Though it’s oriented toward the future, and is fueled by excitable speculation about the implications of the latest science and technology, its roots can be glimpsed in ancient stories like that of the Sumerian king Gilgamesh and his quest for immortality…. Transhumanism represents a desire to obliterate the boundary between human bodies and machines, and a confusion in the first place as to the distinction between the two (Guardian, 2018).
5

Introduction

6 By “essentially embodied Kantian selves,” I mean necessarily and completely embodied rational conscious, self-conscious, sensible (i.e., sense-perceiving, imagining, and emoting), volitional or willing, discursive (i.e., conceptualizing, judging, and inferring) animals, or persons, innately possessing dignity, and fully capable not only of free agency, but also of a priori knowledge of analytic and synthetic a priori truths alike, with egocentric centering in manifestly real orientable space and time. The basic theory of essentially embodied Kantian selves was spelled out by Kant over the course of slightly less than two decades—between 1768 and 1787—in the proto-Critical 1768 essay, “Concerning the Ultimate Ground of the Differentiation of Directions in Space,” in the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Transcendental Analytic, especially including the Deduction of the Pure Concepts of the Understanding, in the Critique of Pure Reason in 1781 (i.e., the first or A edition) and 1787 (i.e., the second or B edition), and in the 1786 essay, “What is Orientation in Thinking,” but above all, it flows from an empirical realist and metaphysical reading of the “Refutation of Idealism” that Kant inserted into the Postulates of Empirical Thought section in the 1787 edition of the first Critique—henceforth, for convenience, “the RI.” This basic theory is also supplemented and supported by practical accounts of essentially embodied Kantian selves that can be found in the Critique of Practical Reason, the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Religion Within the Bounds of Mere Reason, and the Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View.
7 Or as the pre-Critical Kant much more compactly puts it in 1766: “My soul is wholly in my whole body, and wholly in each of its [organic] parts (DSS 2: 325 italics in the original, bracketted word taken from the original source quoted by Kant, cited in the editorial note on p. 449, n. 11).
8 In my opinion, all rational but also “human, all-too-human” creatures like us—for example, the readers of this essay—are, synthetic a priori necessarily,1 essentially embodied Kantian selves. Let’s call that the essentially embodied Kantian selves thesis, or for short, EEKST. If EEKST is true, then it’s synthetic a priori impossible for the selves of creatures like us to exist independently of our own living organismic animal bodies or beyond the deaths of those bodies, whether temporarily or permanently, by any means whatsoever. Indeed, the very ideas of disembodied selves, their survival after death, and of human immortality, while minimally logically consistent, are in fact conceptually empty and incoherent, even over and above the synthetic a priori impossibility of such things, since the term “myself” indexically picks out an essentially embodied Kantian self, all of whose core features require grounding in a particular living organismic animal body. 1. For a full presentation and detailed defense of the analytic-synthetic distinction, including the synthetic a priori, see (Hanna, 2001, and 2015: esp. ch. 4).

всего просмотров: 774

Оценка читателей: голосов 0

1. Block, N. (ed.) (1980) Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology. 2 vols., Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press. Vol. 1.

2. Britannica (2022) “Transhumanism.” .

3. Carruthers, P. (1998) Natural Theories of Consciousness. European Journal of Philosophy 6: 203–220.

4. Chalmers, D. (1996) The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford Univ. Press.

5. Gambarotto, A. and Nahas, A. (2022) Teleology and the Organism: On Kant’s Controversial Legacy for Contemporary Biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 93: 47–56. .

6. Gare, A. (2016) “Beyond Modernism and Postmodernism: The Narrative of Re-embodiments,” in R. Thomas-Pellicer, V. De Lucia and S. Sullivan (eds.), Contributions to Law, Philosophy and Ecology: Exploring Re-Embodiments. London: Routledge. Ch. 1. Pp.27–46. Also available online .

7. Gödel, K. (1967) “On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems,” in J. van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel. Cambridge MA: Harvard Univ. Press. Pp. 596–617.

8. O’Connell, M. (2018) Five Books to Understand Transhumanism. The Guardian. 10 May. .

9. Hacking, I. (1990) The Taming of Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

10. Hanna, R. (2001) Kant and the Foundations of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford Univ. Press.

11. Hanna, R. (2000) Kant and Nonconceptual Content. European Journal of Philosophy 13: 247–290.

12. (Hanna, 2006). Hanna, R. Kant, Science, and Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon/Oxford Univ. Press.

13. Hanna, R. (2008) Kantian Non-Conceptualism. Philosophical Studies 137: 41–64.

14. Hanna, R. (2009) Freedom, Teleology, and Rational Causation. Kant Yearbook 1: 99–142.

15. Hanna, R. (2011) Minding the Body. Philosophical Topics 39: 15–40.

16. Hanna, R. (2014) Kant’s Anti-Mechanism and Kantian Anti-Mechanism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science 45. .

17. Hanna, R. (2015) Cognition, Content, and the A Priori: A Study in the Philosophy of Mind and Knowledge. The Rational Human Condition, Vol. 5. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.

18. Hanna, R. (2016) “Directions in Space, Non-Conceptual Form, and the Foundations of Transcendental Idealism,” in D. Schulting (ed.), Kantian Nonconceptualism. London: Palgrave Macmillan. Pp. 99–115.

19. Hanna, R. (2022) The Philosophy of the Future: Uniscience and the Modern World. Unpublished MS. .

20. Hanna, R. and Maiese, M. (2009) Embodied Minds in Action. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.

21. James, W. (1950) Principles of Psychology. 2 vols., New York: Dover.

22. Kim, J. (2011) Philosophy of Mind. 3rd edn., Boulder, CO: Westview.

23. Moore, G.E. (1993) ‘‘The Refutation of Idealism,” in G.E. Moore, G. E. Moore: Selected Writings. London: Routledge. Pp. 23–44.

24. Nagel, T. (1979) ‘‘What is it Like to be a Bat?’’ in T. Nagel, Mortal Questions Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. Pp. 165–80.

25. Rockwell, T. (2005) Neither Brain Nor Ghost: A Nondualist Alternative to the Mind–Brain Identity Theory. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

26. Sartre. J.-P. (1987) The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness. Trans. F. Williams and R. Kirkpatrick. New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Geroux.

27. Senderowicz, Y. (2021) The “I” that Thinks: Kant on Self-Reference as a Thinker. Iyyun: The Jerusalem Philosophy Quarterly 69: 221–247.

28. Swedenborg Foundation (2022) “Who Was Swedenborg?” .

29. Wikipedia (2022) “Transhumanism.” .

Система Orphus

Загрузка...
Вверх